Robert H. Bork. The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law. Free Press, 1990. See here to purchase the book.
Robert H. Bork was a professor at Yale Law School, a Solicitor
General, and an appellate court judge in the District of Columbia. In
1987, President Ronald Reagan nominated him to the U.S. Supreme Court.
He was a controversial choice, as many deemed him to be overly
right-wing, and he was rejected by the U.S. Senate. His historic
confirmation battle is still mentioned when Republican Presidents
nominate someone to the U.S. Supreme Court, including today, with
President Donald Trump’s choice of Brett Kavanaugh.
In the Tempting of America, Bork explains his judicial
philosophy of originalism. Essentially, Bork maintains that courts
should interpret the U.S. Constitution according to its original
understanding, rather than their preferences for how the country should
be. He is critical of judicial attempts to create rights that are not
explicitly in the U.S. Constitution, particularly the right to privacy,
which undergirds Roe vs. Wade. The book also has an autobiographical
component, as Bork provides some details about his professional
background and offers his own perspective on his confirmation battle, as
well as its aftermath. Not surprisingly, Bork believes that he was
treated unfairly and that his record was distorted by his opponents. He
fears that the legacy of his battle is that judges will continue to
create law from the bench rather than interpret it, and that legal
scholars will be discouraged from being honest and open with their legal
opinions as that could open them up to attack and distortion.
This review will comment on select chapters. It will not be
comprehensive, but it will highlight points that the chapters made,
discussing when appropriate how they coincide with themes elsewhere in
the book.
Chapter 1: “Creation and Fall”
This chapter opens with Bork’s critical look at an opinion by Justice
Samuel Chase in 1798. According to Bork, Chase “was prepared to strike
down laws that violated no provision in any constitution, federal or
state” (page 19). Chase’s rationale flowed not from legal
interpretation but rather from his concept of the “great first
principles of the social compact” (Chase’s words). Bork proceeds to
narrate the origins of judicial review, the idea that the U.S. Supreme
Court can review government laws and actions on the basis of their
consistency or lack thereof with the U.S. Constitution. This goes back
to the 1803 U.S. Supreme Court decision, Marbury vs. Madison. Bork
states that, “In order to reach that issue, [Chief Justice John]
Marshall had not only to ignore the fact that his Court had absolutely
no jurisdiction, he had as well to distort the statute in order to make
it a fit subject for a holding of unconstitutionality” (page 23). Bork
is still understanding about Marshall’s approach, as the United States
was in its infancy and its structures and existence were on the line.
Now that the country is established, Bork does not believe that
Marshall’s overreach should be applied by judges, though he does note
that even judicial review supports the rule of law, not unelected
judges’ subjective ideas about how the country should be.
The 1857 U.S. Supreme Court decision, Dred Scott vs. Sandford,
exemplifies the poor legal reasoning that Bork criticizes. Chief
Justice Roger Taney declared that the slave Dred Scott needed to be
returned to his slavemaster, even though Scott had been in a free
state. The reason was that Scott was the master’s property, and, under
the Fifth Amendment, no one shall be deprived by the federal government
of life, liberty, and property without due process. Bork believes that
Taney is misapplying the due process clause: it is about receiving a
fair trial and has nothing to do with a person having an absolute right
to property, free from federal intervention. After the Fourteenth
Amendment declared that states, too, cannot deprive people of life,
liberty, and property without due process, the Supreme Court continued
to misinterpret and misapply due process. In the late nineteenth
century, the U.S. Supreme Court struck down state regulations to protect
workers, claiming that they violated liberty and property. Bork’s
discussion here coincides with a point that he makes elsewhere in the
book: that judicial activism and overreach are not only things that
liberals do, for conservatives have done them, too.
Chapter 2: “The New Deal Court and the Constitutional Revolution”
The Tenth Amendment establishes federalism: specific powers are given
to the national government by the U.S. Constitution, and the powers not
delegated to the national government are reserved to the states and the
people. Bork appears to see value in this principle: people could vote
with their feet. If they did not like how a state did things, they can
move to another state. The New Deal sought to centralize power in
Washington D.C., and a number of judges thought that it exceeded the
powers that the U.S. Constitution gave to the federal government. The
Supreme Court struck down certain laws of the New Deal as
unconstitutional, but President Franklin Roosevelt eventually got
justices on the Supreme Court who upheld his policies. Bork believes
that the new court misapplied the Commerce Clause, which permits
Congress to regulate interstate commerce. According to Bork, “a
regulation of commerce had to be done for commercial reasons and not as a
means of effecting social or moral regulation,” as the New Deal was
doing (page 56).
Bork’s view on the role of the federal government is rather nebulous,
at least in this book. On the one hand, he seems to believe that the
national government should only do what the U.S. Constitution
specifies. On the other hand, on page 147, he treats the 1964 Civil
Rights Act as a legitimate statute, which expanded people’s rights
beyond what the U.S. Constitution specified. The U.S. Constitution
prohibited federal and state discrimination against people on the basis
of race but not private discrimination, as the Civil Rights Act did.
For Bork, legislation, not judicial activism, is the correct way to give
people more rights than what are in the U.S. Constitution. At some
point in the book, Bork denies that the Supreme Court today should
overturn the New Deal and the Great Society, as these have become
established institutions in society and to overturn them would be
catastrophic for the national order. Roe vs. Wade, by contrast, is a
polarizing decision, as people are divided over whether abortion should
be legal, so Bork supports its overturn, thereby making abortion a
matter for the legislature. Overall, Bork believes that the courts
should sin no more rather than dramatically overturning previous
mistakes, but what does sinning no more mean? Is Congress under the
Tenth Amendment forbidden to create new welfare programs, or new federal
attempts to solve problems?
Bork in this chapter also discusses the 1942 Supreme Court decision,
Skinner vs. Oklahoma. The Court here struck down an Oklahoma statute
requiring the sterilization of two-time felons. “A certain Skinner,”
Bork narrates, “had been convicted of felonies three times, once for
stealing chickens and twice for robbery with firearms” (page 62). The
Court ruled that this statute violated the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment, as it distinguished what crimes deserved
sterilization and what crimes did not: “The three-time larcenist was
subject to sterilization, the three-time embezzler was not” (page 63).
Moreover, the law, according to Justice William Douglas, violated “one
of the basic civil rights of man” (Douglas’s words). Bork disputes the
Court’s legal reasoning. For one, the Fourteenth Amendment is about
racial discrimination, not the right of states to distinguish among
crimes. Second, there is no constitutional right to fertility.
This is a difficult point-of-view to accept. It resembles Bork’s
views on other issues: there is no constitutional right for married
couples to use birth control, there is no constitutional right to engage
in homosexual sex. A key question is this: are there basic human
rights that go beyond what is explicitly in the U.S. Constitution? Bork
shares a story about a student asking him if, under his view, a state
government could prohibit marriage, since a right to marry is not
explicitly in the U.S. Constitution. Bork replied that the framers
would not have conceived that the government could be so tyrannical.
Should a belief that certain government acts are simply tyrannical guide
courts in their assessment of laws, even if the U.S. Constitution does
not explicitly touch on them?
The Ninth Amendment states that the Bill of Rights does not abrogate
rights that are not explicitly in the U.S. Constitution. Bork thinks
that appeals to this argument are better than other legal scholars’
arguments against originalism that are out there. Still, Bork believes
that this argument, too, falls short. The Ninth Amendment, he argues,
was saying that the Bill of Rights does not abrogate rights that the
states already recognize, not allowing federal courts to create new
rights that are absent from the U.S. Constitution.
Chapter 3: “The Warren Court: The Political Role Embraced”
Bork in this chapter defends Brown vs. the Board of Education, the
landmark decision that prohibited racial discrimination in public
schools. He has issues with the Warren Court’s rationale behind that
decision, but he agrees with the decision itself. Bork acknowledges
that, originally, the Fourteenth Amendment was not intended to prohibit
racially segregated schools. Still, it was intended to prohibit the
government from racially discriminating, and racially segregated public
schools, in effect, were doing that. This discussion coincides with
Bork’s explanation of originalism: that it is not entirely about the
original intent of the law’s framers but is also about what the law
says, and the principle that the law sets forth. Elsewhere in this
chapter (and in the book), Bork will embrace a similar approach to what
he does with Brown: he will say that there is a legitimate, originalist
way to arrive at a progressive goal. He thinks that the Warren Court
overreached in a decision about legislative districting, but he
acknowledges that the Court can constitutionally challenge districting
that severely undermines the rights of majorities to choose their own
leaders. He did not care for the reasoning that courts used to strike
down discriminatory racial covenants, seeing it as arbitrary and
detached from the law, but he did say that there was a legal basis to
challenge racial covenants, due to statutes on the books.
Bork’s personal experiences and ideological evolution are mentioned
in this chapter. Bork tells a humorous story about a time when he was
asked to redistrict a state. He also talks about how he changed his
mind on an issue of constitutional law: he used to believe that court
decisions should follow a consistent neutral principle (liberty) in
evaluating laws, but now he thinks that courts should simply stick with
what the law says.
The right to privacy is introduced in this chapter. Griswold vs.
Connecticut struck down a law criminalizing the usage of contraception
by married couples. Bork states that this law was not taken seriously
or rigorously enforced (he later says the same about the anti-sodomy law
that Bowers vs. Hardwick affirmed), but that people decided to
challenge it in order to advance their own sexually individualist
agenda. Bork argues that there is no right to privacy in the U.S.
Constitution, and he notes that a lot of laws legitimately challenge
privacy: people cannot use drugs in the privacy of their own homes, for
example, or abuse their wives or kids. Bork raises a good point there.
Still, the Constitution in the Third and Fourth Amendments does seem to
value privacy. Bork could say that the Fourth Amendment related to
criminal investigations and not a general right to privacy, but perhaps a
regard for privacy undergirds what the Fourth Amendment says about
criminal investigation.
Speaking of criminal investigation, Bork is critical of the Warren
Court’s decisions on the right to remain silent and the exclusionary
rule. He does not provide much detail in this discussion about the
rationale for his views. He seems to disagree mildly with the view that
the Fourteenth Amendment applies to the states the Bill of Rights, and
yet he accepts that as the lesser of two evils: it is better to say that
the states must follow the Bill of Rights, than to say that courts can
invent new rights that are not explicitly in the Constitution.
Chapter 4: “After Warren: The Burger and Rehnquist Courts”
Bork criticizes Supreme Court decisions that allowed for racial
quotas, seeing those as violations of the Civil Rights Act. He
criticizes Roe vs. Wade. He states that he himself does not support
criminalizing homosexual sex but that states have a right to do so. He
states that a Texas law banning flag burning did not violate the First
Amendment: “Texas had not prohibited the desecration of the American
flag because the idea expressed was offensive but because the mode of
expression was” (page 127). The topic of the First Amendment will recur
in this book. Bork said that pornography was not protected by the
First Amendment, yet he seemed to acknowledge that seemingly
non-political speech or expression that is provocative may be protected
because it is making a political statement. Bork wrote that the First
Amendment does not protect encouraging people to break the law, since
the presumption behind the First Amendment is the rule of law: speaking
out and debating what laws are appropriate for society. People
criticized Bork on this, saying that he was criticizing civil
disobedience and that his view would entail that Martin Luther King,
Jr.’s civil disobedience lacked First Amendment protection. Bork
replied that King was not undermining the rule of law but was
challenging segregation laws as being inconsistent with the U.S.
Constitution.
Chapter 7: “The Original Understanding”
Bork makes this clarification of original understanding on page 144:
“If someone found a letter from George Washington to Martha telling her
that what he meant by the power to lay taxes was not what other people
meant, that would not change our reading of the Constitution in the
slightest…When lawmakers use words, the law that results is what the
words ordinarily mean.”
Chapter 8: “Objections to Original Understanding”
One argument Bork addresses is that the Constitution must change as
society changes. Bork asks a good question: can we truly say that
society is changing on a given topic, when the Supreme Court is striking
down laws that people through their representatives enacted? For
example, let’s take the death penalty. Some argue that we are more
civilized now and so we should interpret the Constitution as banning the
death penalty, even though the Constitution presumes the legitimacy of
the death penalty. But Bork asks: is society now truly against the
death penalty? People through their elected representatives have
supported it! Bork does not think that liberal judges are following the
new consensus of society but rather their own controversial morality,
which cannot win at the ballot box.
A question that I wish Bork had addressed more deeply is how we can
discern original intent, when the framers themselves seemed to disagree
about aspects of constitutional interpretation. Some preferred a strict
interpretation of the Tenth Amendment, while others were not so
strict. Some thought that the First Amendment banned Congress from
having chaplains, whereas others were not so draconian.
Chapters 14-16 contain Bork’s telling of his confirmation battle.
There were humorous anecdotes. Bork says that he was patient in
discussing the First Amendment with Senator Arlen Specter, and that
people might mistake their conversation for a serious constitutional
discussion, when Specter was completely missing Bork’s point. Bork
talks about Joe Biden’s withdrawal from the 1988 Presidential race due
to charges of plagiarism, and how Biden told the embattled Bork that
their situations were similar. Bork could not see the similarity! Bork
also talks about how people have confused him with Surgeon General
Koop, and Koop with him, because they both have beards! Bork defends
himself from the accusation that he consistently ruled against
minorities and labor, highlighting numerous examples to the contrary.
He rejects that idea that he was outside of the mainstream, noting the
Ivy League professors and Supreme Court justices who supported his
nomination.
This review has not covered several of Bork’s attempts to refute
arguments against originalism. If Bork’s portrayal of those arguments
is accurate, then those arguments are pretty weak! The book could get
tedious, but it is still worthwhile to read.